´óÏã½¶É«È˸ó

    1. <form id=LYiWIujZJ><nobr id=LYiWIujZJ></nobr></form>
      <address id=LYiWIujZJ><nobr id=LYiWIujZJ><nobr id=LYiWIujZJ></nobr></nobr></address>

      Talk delivered at the Touch Me Festival, Zagreb, December 2008
      The Reproductive Revolution: selection pressure in a Post-Darwinian World

      The Reproductive Revolution
      Selection Pressure in a Post-Darwinian World

      Here are three predictions about life one thousand years from now:

      1) Suffering of any kind will be biologically impossible. Our descendants will lead lives of genetically pre-programmed bliss whose worst lows surpass today's peak experiences. A thousand years hence, the heritable hedonic set-point of ordinary waking life will have been ratcheted upwards so that everyday existence feels sublime.

      2) Our genetically enhanced successors won't grow old and die, but will be effectively immortal, barring accidents which mean certain brains have to be restored from digital backup.

      3) Posthumans will be innately smarter than us, not just in the narrow autistic sense of intelligence measured by contemporary IQ tests, but also a more empathetic intelligence. To use a non-scientific term, our descendants will be "wiser" than contemporary humans.

      These are bold claims. They could of course be completely mistaken: futurology doesn't have a brilliant track-record. However, I'm going to argue why these three seemingly unrelated developments - superhappiness, superlongevity and superintelligence - are intimately linked. We are on the brink of a revolution in reproductive medicine - the coming era of designer babies, a fundamental transition in the evolution of life in the universe. Evolution will shortly cease to be "blind" and "random", as it has been for the past four billion years. Instead, intelligent agents are going to choose and design genotypes in anticipation of their likely behavioural and psychological effects. Specifically, prospective parents will increasingly choose the genetic makeup of their future children rather than playing genetic roulette. Natural selection is going to be replaced by "unnatural" selection.

      But first, let us outline a very different, bioconservative vision, perhaps best represented today by the distinguished geneticist at University College London, Professor Steve Jones.

      Two Contrasting Views of Future Human Evolution

      1) BIOCONSERVATIVISM: ["The End of Evolution"?] "If you want to know what Utopia is like, just look around - this is it", says Professor Jones in a Royal Society debate in Edinburgh. In a talk1 entitled "Is Evolution Over?" Prof. Jones says: "Things have simply stopped getting better, or worse, for our species." Professor Jones explains how there were three components to human evolution ¨C natural selection, mutation and random change. ¡°Quite unexpectedly, we have dropped the human mutation rate because of a change in reproductive patterns.¡±

      ¡°In ancient times half our children would have died by the age of 20. Now, in the Western world, 98 per cent of them are surviving to 21¡±, says Professor Jones in a recent interview2 with The Times. The mutation rate is also slowing down. Although chemicals and radioactive pollution could cause genetic changes, one of the most important mutation triggers was advanced age in men. "Perhaps surprisingly, the age of reproduction has gone down - the mean age of male reproduction means that most conceive no children after the age of 35. Fewer older fathers means that if anything, mutation is going down."

      It's worth adding that some scientists and right-wing commentators go further than Steve Jones. They argue that because nominally more intelligent people have fewer children than nominally less intelligent people, then the intelligence of the human species as a whole is actually going to decline. This prediction isn't borne out by the long-term increase in IQ scores over the last century, the "Flynn Effect". However, believers in the so-called dysgenic fertility hypothesis counter that it is possible for genotypic IQ to decline even while phenotypic IQ rises throughout the population, at least in the short run. They explain this paradox by environmental effects such as better schooling, improved nutrition, and even television viewing.

      By contrast to the bioconservative perspective:

      2) BIOREVOLUTION: Human evolution is about to accelerate. Selection pressure isn't going to slacken. On the contrary, we're on the eve an era of unnatural or artificial selection - a different kind of selection pressure, but a selection pressure that will be extraordinarily intense, favouring a very different set of adaptations than traits that were genetically adaptive in the ancestral environment on the African savannah.

      Let's quickly review some background. The Human Genome Project (HGP) was the international scientific research project that aimed to determine the sequence of chemical base pairs of our DNA: the genetic make-up of our species. Researchers identified, physically and functionally, the 25,000 or so genes of the human genome. The project was formally declared complete to a 99.99% accuracy in 2003, though in reality there are a lot of loose ends to be tied up. The full implications of our deciphered code have scarcely been glimpsed. They may take centuries to unravel.

      Currently [2009], if you want your whole genome of three billion odd base pairs sequenced, the price is several thousand dollars. This figure is prohibitively expensive for most people. [In 2015, the price had fallen to around one thousand dollars.] But in a decade or so, the cost on some estimates could be as little as ten dollars. Whatever the exact price or timing, the cost of access to one's own source code is poised to collapse. Routine access to one's personal genome will usher in an era of personalised medicine - individual drugs, dosages and gene therapies targeted at the individual rather than the scatter-gun approach we see in clinical pharmacology (and recreational drug use) today.

      Yet we're not just heading for an era of personalized medicine - we're on the eve of an era of personalized reproductive medicine: "designer babies", to use the popular term. The phrase suggests something frivolous, akin to designer clothes. But choosing the genetic make-up of your child may soon become the badge of responsible parenthood - as distinct from throwing the genetic dice and hoping they roll the right way, as now. A reluctance to pass on harmful code to our children won't just apply to obvious autosomal dominant conditions like the neurological disorder Huntington's disease. What prospective parent, if offered the choice, is deliberately going to pass on genes for haemophilia, sickle-cell anaemia or muscular dystrophy? It has been estimated that on average we each carry four lethal recessive genes. In a future of post-genomic reproductive medicine, the selection pressure against, say, the cystic fibrosis allele, the cause of the most common life-limiting autosomal recessive disease among people of European heritage, is going to become intense, as indeed is selection pressure against a whole range of genes that cause or contribute to physical disease. Currently, we're used to Googling prospective partners on the Net to find out more about them. Looking ahead, what responsible prospective parent will neglect to check their partner's DNA - and their own - before having children? This doesn't mean that anyone who wants a child will reject an asymptomatic partner who carries a recessive copy of a "nasty" gene. Instead, responsible parents can use preimplantation genetic diagnosis and germline gene therapy to ensure that potentially harmful genes like the recessive cystic fibrosis allele aren't passed on to their children.

      Genetic Roulette versus Designer Babies

      Yet how about heritable psychological traits, "personality genes", that contribute to psychological pain? Not merely is there no consensus on whether some of their less pleasant variants should be classed as pathological, here too things are much more complex technically than for monogenic disorders like cystic fibrosis. This is because there is no such thing as a single gene "for" depression or anxiety disorders or jealousy or obsessive compulsive disorder (OCD) and so forth. But there are alleles and genotypes that predispose to depression or anxiety disorders or jealousy or obsessive compulsive disorder - and other polygenic, multifactorial psychological conditions. So if there is a particular allele - a variant gene - that makes it, say, 5% more likely that a particular trait such as low mood or chronic anxiety will be expressed, or an allele that makes its bearer 5% more or less anxious or more or less depressive, then what percentage of prospective parents will purposely choose the less pleasant variant for their children? Yes, there are numerous complications, for instance pleiotropy, where a single gene influences multiple phenotypic traits; alternative splicing, whereby a single gene may produce different proteins in different settings; genomic imprinting, a parent-dependent form of gene expression; non-Mendelian inheritance in the form of transgenerational epigenetic effects; and so forth. More generally, critics of the new genetic medicine worry about creating "designer personalities". Other things being equal, however, most informed parents will presumably choose the more compassionate option for their child. Indeed one Oxford Professor of Ethics goes further. Julian Savulescu argues that we are are morally obligated to select genetic blueprints for children with the greatest chance of leading the best life: what Prof. Savulescu dubs the Principle of Procreative Beneficence.

      This conjecture isn't premature. For example, people who inherit two copies of a "short" version of the chromosome 17 serotonin transporter gene, 5-HTTLPR, have an 80 per cent chance of becoming clinically depressed if they experience three or more negative life-events in five years. By contrast, genetically resilient people who inherit the long version have only a 30 per cent chance of developing mental illness in similar circumstances. If offered the choice via preimplantation diagnosis (PGD), would you opt for the short or the long serotonin transporter gene variant for your future child? Or would you decline to choose, putting your faith in God or Mother Nature?

      Right now, of course, this kind of scenario still sounds far-fetched. Later this century and beyond, are prospective parents really going to enroll for courses in behavioural genetics and molecular biopsychiatry before having kids? For sure, certain genetic decisions are in principle straightforward, for example gender selection, or whether to pass on a cystic fibrosis allele. Such decisions are taken by some prospective parents in a few countries already. But other genetic decisions will be much more complicated, not least for "mood genes" that help determine a person's average level of well-being or ill-being over a lifetime.

      For what it's worth, I personally think that taking advanced courses in behavioural genetics, or at least seeking genetic counselling, will be morally incumbent on anyone before s/he assumes the immense responsibility of having a child. Yet this kind of education is unlikely to be widespread for the foreseeable future. The argument presented here doesn't depend on it. Instead, in an era of mature reproductive medicine, we may forecast an abundance of user-friendly software tools to enable prospective parents to take responsible genetic decisions - as distinct from blindly taking their chances in the genetic lottery of Darwinian life. For the exponential growth in computing power can be harnessed to a new growth industry of sophisticated baby-authoring software. So the average parent will no more be required to understand molecular genetics than the average contemporary Windows PC user is required to understand machine code. And the parallel goes further. If it's ethically acceptable to spend hours redesigning your Windows PC desktop the way you like it, then why not at least take a few hours to make sure that your future child is psychologically and physically healthy too?

      Of course, such authoring tools open up an ethical and regulatory minefield of gargantuan proportions. Yet so does sexual reproduction: playing the genetic equivalent of Russian roulette with a child's life.

      Recalibrating the Hedonic Treadmill.
      OK, maybe prospective parents will choose to avoid alleles and allelic combinations associated with depression or anxiety disorders or schizophrenia when they prepare to have children. But what grounds are there for thinking that the average hedonic set-point of humankind as a whole will be ratcheted ever upwards? Recall that we all have a kind of inbuilt hedonic treadmill that prevents most of us from remaining extremely happy or extremely miserable for very long - though of course extreme misery can seem like an eternity while it lasts. Our hedonic treadmill tends to have an approximate hedonic set-point around which we fluctuate over time. This hedonic set-point crudely determines the average level of subjective well-being or ill-being that most people experience throughout a lifetime. Of course we're all buffeted by external events, both pleasant and unpleasant, that affect us acutely for good or ill; but over time, we mostly revert to a [partly] heritable individual mean. In some people, the hedonic set-point tends to be fixed below the Darwinian average: such people have a gloomy temperament - what the ancients would have called an excess of black bile. In other people, the hedonic set-point is fixed above average: they are temperamentally optimistic. Some people's mood oscillates sharply, other people are more equable. But the current range of hedonic diversity aside, why may we predict that the typical default state of well-being of the human population is going to increase indefinitely - even after genes predisposing to anxiety disorders and clinical depression have been weeded out of the gene-pool?

      The plain answer is that we can't know for sure. So this is speculation. Yet here is a thought-experiment. Imagine that you have the option of choosing the genetic dial-settings of the hedonic set-point of your future child: the degree to which he or she is temperamentally depressive or happy - or superhappy. To keep things simple, I won't yet consider the richer forms of emotional well-being, just normal hedonic tone, which we know is partly heritable. What average level of hedonic tone would you choose for your future child on a 10-point scale? [Here again I am being deliberately simplistic.] On the unscientific basis of a few straw polls conducted over the years, I'd estimate that most people if pressed would opt for a hedonic 8 or 9. Yet a surprising number of respondents say "10": they would like their children to be as temperamentally happy as possible.

      Realistically, perhaps only a minority of prospective parents will initially want to have children disposed to be naturally superhappy by contemporary norms. But most parents will want happy children, as distinct from depressive, moody, anxiety-ridden children. Not least, happy children are more fun to raise. Happy, resilient, self-confident children are also more likely to be "successful" over-achievers in the traditional Darwinian sense: we needn't suppose that prospective parents care only about the happiness of their future kids: many parents-to-be are of course highly ambitious for their offspring. Anyhow, on this argument, the average, genetically constrained set-point of emotional well-being of our species is destined to rise over time as a reflection of these individual parental choices, as tomorrow's enhancement technologies shift social norms of well-being and become the next generation's remedial therapies. The depressive realism of one century may become the affective psychosis of the next. Over time, an analogous selection pressure may be exerted in favour of alleles and allelic combinations predisposing to high intelligence - and perhaps even genius and supergenius - although here any contribution to enhanced quality of life will be indirect. In any event, over a whole spectrum of physical and psychological traits, we may predict that germline enhancement will become germline remediation as the average level of biological well-being improves across human society. As biophysicist Gregory Stock notes in Redesigning Humans (2002), "The arrival of safe, reliable germline technology will [...] transform the evolutionary process by drawing reproduction into a highly selective social process that is far more rapid and effective at spreading successful genes than traditional sexual competition and mate selection." Thus the tempo of world-wide mood-enrichment may accelerate.

      Critically, the genetic mood-enrichment conjecture doesn't hypothesise the future existence of any mega-project to make a happier world. The possibility of such a pan-global project can't be excluded - grandiose and fanciful as the idea of some kind of Hedonistic Imperative (1995) now sounds. Currently only the tiny Himalayan kingdom of Bhutan officially exalts Gross National Happiness (GNH) over Gross National Product (GNP). If hedonic enrichment were internationalized and pursued with scientific rigour, then the selection pressure against nastier Darwinian genotypes would be even more severe than anticipated here. Now personally, I advocate a world-wide Abolitionist Project laid down as official United Nations policy. Not least, only a global mega-project can ever extend the abolition of suffering to the rest of the living world. Ecosystem redesign, cross-species depot-contraception, and eventually rewriting the whole vertebrate genome can't be achieved via private initiative. However, such a mega-project isn't imminent. Less extravagantly, global mood-enrichment may be the collective outcome of billions of personal reproductive decisions made by individual parents-to-be during the next century and beyond.

      Phrased in the language of designer babies, the prospect of species-wide hedonic enrichment evokes sinister images - even though it promises to make the world a much happier place. Do we really want parents controlling the destiny of their future children? But we have to be careful about how we frame the issue here. Just as physical good health is empowering, and doesn't determine what you do with your life, likewise being temperamentally happy and psychologically robust doesn't determine what you actually do with your life either. Like physical health, mental health tends to empower rather than constrain. Genetically hardwired mental superhealth is potentially even more empowering. It makes you psychologically indestructible. It stops you ever becoming depressed or anxiety-ridden - and suffering the crippling loss of life-opportunities that such conditions entail. Moreover, in the future anybody who isn't satisfied with aspects of their core personality, and who doesn't want to use consciousness-altering drugs to change it, can practise somatic gene therapy. We won't always be at the mercy of a scrambled mix of our parent's genes as now, whether those genes have been passed on by accident or design.

      Future Nociception: The End of Physical Pain?

      So far I've talked about the abolition of suffering, and how psychological pain can be genetically eliminated over time. But what about the terrible scourge of raw physical pain? Surely, the sceptic might wonder, genes that promote pain-sensitivity in response to tissue damage will be as adaptive one thousand years from now as they are today - and as they were in the ancestral environment. So the prediction that one thousand years hence, the worst experiences that anyone undergoes will be richer than today's peak experiences sounds like a pipe-dream. How is this even technically possible, let alone sociologically realistic?

      Well, there is a short-to-medium term answer and a longer-term answer. Let's consider the short-to-medium term options first.

      The Cyborg Solution versus Radical Recalibration.
      At present there are different "natural" genetic variants that promote varying degrees of pain-sensitivity e.g. variant alleles of the gene SCN9A coding for the a-subunit of the voltage-gated sodium channel Nav1.7 in nociceptive neurons; the mu opioid receptor gene; and the gene encoding catecholamine-O-methyltransferase (COMT). Few prospective parents in the future are going to want kids who are hypersensitive to physical pain. Most parents, if given the choice, will presumably seek no more than mild-to-modest pain-sensitivity for their offspring. Thus if genetically planned parenthood ever becomes the norm, then our pain thermostats (or "algostats", as one might call them) are likely to be genetically re-set over time too.

      But this recalibration doesn't actually abolish suffering, it just diminishes its prevalence and intensity when physical pain occurs. Moreover, as attested by rare cases of congenital anaesthesia, children born without any capacity to suffer pain are currently liable to undergo all manner of life-threatening medical complications. So does this mean we are stuck with pain in some guise or other for ever?

      No, though there are formidable technical challenges to overcome. If we are to abolish physical pain altogether, I think there are two long-term options. These two options are not mutually exclusive, but I will consider them separately. Recall how silicon (etc.) robots with the right functional architecture can get by fine without the nasty "raw feels" of phenomenal pain; they can be programmed to avoid and respond flexibly and adaptively to noxious stimuli. Clearly, there is a distinction between the physiological function of nociception and the subjective experience of phenomenal pain; they are dissociable even in organic robots like us, not just our inorganic counterparts. So likewise, in theory future humans could computationally offload everything nasty or routine onto prosthetic devices, nanobots and the like, preserving only the life-enriching forms of sentience and discarding the ugly Darwinian junk. This is what we may call the Cyborg Solution. The main advantage of the Cyborg Solution in the long run is that it permits maximum lifelong bliss for all sentient life. Thus its ultimate adoption would seem mandatory on a classical utilitarian ethic. But assuming that we don't go down the cyborg route, there is another option. In principle, we can radically reset the scale of the pleasure-pain axis in the mind/brain. All that is needed for an organism to respond adaptively to a changing and potentially hostile environment is informational-sensitivity to fitness-relevant changes - including the binary opposition "wonderful" versus "not-quite-as-wonderful" - regardless of the tidal range of our emotions on an absolute hedonic scale; a narrow compass of pleasure gradients can in theory play a role analogous to pain gradients in some victims of chronic pain syndrome today.

      This hypothesis is counterintuitive. One might imagine that if people always feel more-or-less superwell - both physically and psychologically - then they won't be motivated to act circumspectly; and therefore they will tend to hurt themselves, whether physically or emotionally or both. Who could respond adaptively to the world if consumed by a perpetual whole-body orgasm? Yet this doesn't follow. As we know today, the happiest people, the keenest life-lovers, tend to be the most motivated people. It's depressives who tend to be unmotivated. Yes, there are forms of happiness associated with indolence, for example opiated bliss. But there are also forms of happiness associated with intense motivation, forward planning and goal-directed behaviour, so called hyperdopaminergic states. Either way, our descendants, and possibly our elderly selves, will have a choice of what kinds of physical and emotional well-being they want to enjoy, and a choice of what kinds of genetic predisposition to pass on to the next generation. If you don't want to bring any more suffering into the world, then your only option right now is not to have children. In the future, however, we'll be able to have cruelty-free children with a clear conscience - on that score at least.

      Gradients of Bliss?
      What's true of physical pain and depression is true of other negative states of mind. Thus the prediction that life a thousand years hence will feel orders of magnitude better than now isn't a claim that posthumans will all be uniformly happy, or that future life will be perfect, whatever that might mean. Indeed one can argue that discontent is the motor of progress, and that the functional analogues of discontent are likely to endure one thousand years from now, just as the raw feels of discontent exist at present. Admittedly, it's hard to know whether fourth millennium (post)humans will be endowed with anything even functionally resembling the same core emotions that define our lives today. The molecular signature of some kinds of emotion, for example disgust, panic or jealousy, might be abolished altogether, both phenomenally and functionally, whereas genes and regulatory code for novel life-enriching emotions may be customised and spliced into the genome. Our perceptual and cognitive architecture is likely to be genetically reshaped too - probably in ways beyond the contemporary human imagination. But such innovation isn't essential for an improved quality of life. The functional analogues of anxiety and depression could still persist and yet life could always be subjectively wonderful - since it's technically possible to decouple functional role from the subjective texture of unpleasant experience as we feel it now.

      Critically, I'm not arguing that our descendants will enjoy uniform bliss, and certainly not that they will be manic or "blissed out", simply that their genetically constrained floor of comparative ill-being will be higher than our absolute ceiling of well-being. Continual germline-enhancement across the generations will create a novel motivational system. Its mechanisms of emotional homeostasis will transcend the Darwinian pleasure-pain axis. Thanks to the unfolding Reproductive Revolution, there will be continual selection pressure in favour of the biology of a subjectively improved quality of life. Equating net value and net happiness in the manner of classical utilitarian ethics may or may not be simplistic; but acknowledgement of the connection between enhanced value and enhanced emotional well-being is common to a whole range of ethical systems, both religious and secular. Few ethical systems give no weight to emotional well-being. Thus if a piece of music sounds a thousand times more enchanting than its predecessor, or if a work of art looks a thousand times more beautiful to behold than anything physiologically possible at present, then I think the default assumption must be that such overpowering beauty is indeed a good thing - in the absence of cogent arguments to the contrary. The new germinal choice technologies allow the creation of subjectively valuable experience on a truly prodigious scale. So other things being equal, we should embrace their use.

      Spiritual well-being?
      The approach I've sketched so far probably sounds crudely reductionist. But one needn't interpret superhappiness in just a narrow one-dimensional sense. Take, for example, spirituality and spiritual well-being. ? In future, if you are very spiritual and want to have hyperspiritual children, then you can opt to over- or under-express the relevant genes or allelic combinations promoting a spiritual temperament; and perhaps ultimately design angelic "spiritual" genomes for your children. Indeed if you want to be naturally superspiritual yourself and don't want to take entheogenic drugs, then you could use autosomal gene enhancement and add extra copies or over-express variants of alleles and allelic combinations associated with spirituality. Secular rationalists, on the other hand, may prefer to lay the genetic foundations of a more worldly well-being.

      To take another example of multi-dimensional well-being, prospective parents may be able to choose genes and genotypes associated, not just with intelligence in the simple-minded conventional sense, but with an increased capacity for empathy, involving functionally amplified mirror neurons and enhanced social cognition. Prospective parents will have the opportunity to endow their kids with an enriched oxytocin system, leading to greater trust, generosity of spirit, and pro-social behaviour, potentially with immense benefits for society as a whole. Such scenarios are of course speculative.

      A Reproductive Elite?

      An obvious question arises. Won't these new reproductive technologies be solely for the rich, or at least mainly for members of the prosperous developed nations who can buy the best genes, undercutting the argument from selection pressure advanced here?

      Initially, surely yes. But not for long, even assuming [implausibly] that the world's poorest nations will remain poor indefinitely. Consider how rapidly web-enabled cell phones have spread through even impoverished sub-Saharan Africa. If personal genome sequencing always costs anything like the $200,000 it does now [December 2008; year 2013 = c.$10,000], then only an elite of affluent Westerners could benefit from such breakthroughs. If personal genome sequencing cost ten dollars or less, then effectively everyone can have it. The nature of information and information technology entails that IT-based services don't involve the consumption of scarce natural resources in the way material goods do, where one person's gain is frequently another person's loss. Only a handful of people in the world can ever own a Rolls Royce or a Maserati, and even fewer can own an original Picasso or an Old Master; but an unlimited number of people can listen to the world's entire catalogue of music, enjoy access to all its electronic games, its computer software, its movies, or indeed the whole Library of Congress. Information is effectively free, or at least it will be soon. Later this century, reproductive technologies like preimplantation genetic screening (PGS) and diagnosis (PGD) - techniques used to identify genetic defects in embryos created through in vitro fertilization before pregnancy - are going to become dirt-cheap too. Already crude personal genotyping services are available for a few hundred dollars.

      Of course it's easy to sing a happy tune with the word "soon". I'm glossing over a host of problems in the transitional era between old-fashioned sexual reproduction and true planned parenthood. "Soon" in this context may mean decades, and perhaps centuries. But even on the most conservative timescales, we're on the brink of a major discontinuity in the four-billion-year odyssey of the evolution of life on Earth.

      Some Unknowns

      Human Cloning.
      One big unknown affecting any conjectures about future selection pressure is the role of human cloning. Whether human reproductive cloning takes another five years or fifty years, it is going to happen. What's less clear is the cost and expertise involved when the technology matures, and what are its global implications for selection pressure. If human cloning will always take a large team of research professionals, complex medical equipment, many failed attempts and a great deal of money, then it will presumably always be rare. But if it can ever be done cheaply and safely at home, perhaps via DIY cloning kits available for purchase over the Net, then human cloning could become a common way to make babies, regardless of official laws and regulations.

      For the sake of argument, let's suppose that human cloning does eventually become a common mode of reproduction. It's not clear this is a bad development per se, any more than identical twins or triplets are intrinsically bad. Either way, this possibility might seem to throw a big spanner into the argument from selection pressure I'm making here, since genetically identical babies are likely to suffer from the same problems as their father or mother if exposed to a similar environment.

      Yet it seems a reasonable assumption that most future human cloners won't seek to create exact genetic duplicates of themselves, but will instead aspire to have offspring free of defects or unwanted characteristics possessed by their parent. To use a trivial example, a human cloner with thinning hair wouldn't necessarily want to have a cloned child with a predisposition to grow bald. Granted, most Asian people who want a clone will want to have children who are Asian-looking, and most blue-eyed people will probably want blue-eyed clones, but presumably carriers of the cystic fibrosis allele won't seek to pass the defective gene on to their cloned offspring. Likewise, for the most part depressive people who might like to clone themselves aren't likely to want depressive children. Cases of "negative enhancement", akin to the existing use of preimplantation genetic diagnosis to select an embryo for the presence of a particular disability such as deafness shared by the parent(s), will presumably be uncommon. So yes, if human cloning becomes widespread, and certainly if human cloning becomes cheap and ubiquitous, then its spread makes the argument from selection pressure defended here more complex; but the practice wouldn't fundamentally undercut its conclusion.

      Autosomal Gene Therapy and Enhancement.
      Another unknown that adds to the complexity of the selection pressure argument is the future extent of autosomal gene therapy. I've been focusing on reproduction and germ-line gene therapy and genetic enhancement; but somatic gene therapy is sure to become available and probably extensively used too. After all, if offered the choice of either taking a drug to remedy some physical or psychological defect for the rest of your life or curing that deficit with a one-off course of gene therapy, which would you choose - if you were sure that the gene therapy was safe and effective? The same is true of future enhancement technologies - though remediation versus enhancement is a naïve dichotomy.

      Potential Pitfalls

      The Spectre of Coercive Eugenics.
      Anyone uncritically enthusiastic about the Reproductive Revolution in prospect would do well to reflect on the history of the twentieth century. In the words of bioethicist Nicholas Agar, "Those who do not learn from the history of human enhancement may be doomed to repeat it". One recalls the forced segregation, sterilization, racial hygiene, the euthanasia program and ultimately the genocide practised in the pseudo-scientific name of eugenics. Might the impending Reproductive Revolution lead to similar horrors? After all, there are still plenty of people in the world convinced that some races are intellectually or morally superior to other races. Might history repeat itself?

      The short answer is yes, though I think such scenarios are unlikely. For a start, the totalitarian dictatorships of the twentieth century, not least the Third Reich, all depended on censorship and a state-monopoly of information. The Internet makes the creation of totalitarian dictatorships much harder; as has been well said, the Internet interprets censorship as damage and re-routes. However, this is obviously a huge topic. All I'll say here is that there is a fundamental difference between a regulatory system where eugenics [under whatever name] is practised for the well-being of the individual - whether human or non-human - and an authoritarian society where eugenics is practised for the notional benefit of a class, race or nation.

      Even so, there are clearly lots of problems with so-called liberal eugenics. For instance, there are pitfalls with prospective parents choosing enhancements that offer a merely positional advantage to their children. To give a concrete example, if parents pick genes likely to allow their child to grow taller than current average, then there is no net benefit to either the child or society if most other parents do the same. Indeed if human stature were to become significantly higher than today, then we would all be prone to multiple health difficulties under Earth's gravitational regime. Even enhancements such as genes that may contribute to superior intelligence - overexpressing or adding extra copies of the NRP2 or ASPM or microcephalin gene to use a contentious example - that sound as though they could confer intrinsic benefit might arguably amount to positional goods like height. Thus women tend to find intelligence sexy in prospective mates; but presumably what's advantageous to the brainy male bearer in terms of enhanced sex-appeal is relative- and not absolute- intelligence. A counter to this argument might be that there are inherent benefits to high male intelligence aside from attracting women.

      In contrast with interventions that confer positional advantage, genetic enhancements that enrich subjective well-being - crudely, whether you are temperamentally happy or superhappy - would be intrinsically beneficial; they can potentially benefit everyone, regardless of where one falls on any comparative scale of well-being. Indeed technologies that biologically enrich emotional well-being are arguably the only enhancements that are intrinsically good as distinct from positionally or instrumentally good. This claim is obviously controversial; it would be contested by many bioethicists who aren't classical utilitarians.

      Other pitfalls?
      Although designer genomes can in principle lead to vastly greater diversity, might designer genomes lead in practice to greater genetic uniformity - if most parents strive to have similar kinds of "ideal" children, the supernormal reflections of preferences adaptive in our Darwinian past? Admittedly, some kinds of genetic uniformity are presumably desirable. Thus by common consent it would be a blessing if there were no gene for Huntington's disease (HD). But twentieth century eugenicists didn't take account of phenomena such as heterozygote advantage - normally defined as cases where the heterozygote genotype has a higher relative fitness than either the homozygote dominant or homozygote recessive genotype. Heterozygote advantage explains why some kinds of genetic variability persist, most famously the gene for sickle-cell anaemia. Analogous heterozygote advantage may exist for psychological traits too, though this is unproven.

      Whatever their evolutionary origin, here are three examples where the issues are complicated.

      The Future of Homosexuality: Even if you have absolutely no prejudices at all about homosexuality, would you choose so-called gay genes for your child - variant alleles that predispose your child to be gay? Now of course it's possible that in 50 or 150 years time, homophobia will have been relegated to the dustbin of history where it belongs; but I wouldn't count on it. In the meantime, what percentage of prospective parents, whether straight or gay or bisexual, will deliberately choose to have a gay child knowing the greater social problems that child would be likely to encounter in life due to social prejudice? If this is the case, and if there is indeed a Reproductive Revolution as outlined here, then it is quite likely that genes predisposing to homosexuality and possibly even bisexuality will be strongly selected against. They may even die out. If one looks in human history from classical antiquity to the present at the contribution made by people whom we would probably classify as gay or bisexual, and likewise at the contribution of their close genetic relatives, then this is not an outcome to be contemplated lightly. On the other hand, it's also possible that many gay couples will use the new reproductive technologies to have gay children, rendering the gay extinction scenario moot.

      The Future of Bipolar Disorder: Chronic unipolar depression may be an unmitigated evil; but what about Bipolar Disorder, formerly known as manic depression? Bipolar Disorder can undoubtedly cause terrible suffering both to its victims and their families. Yet many creative high achievers in art, science and politics have at the very least been soft bipolars. Is there a danger that something valuable will be lost if in future prospective parents weed out of the gene-pool alleles associated with bipolarity? Again, this is a huge topic.

      The Future of Autism Spectrum Disorders: Classical autism is characterized by varying degrees of "mindblindness" and deficits in social interaction; deficits in language, communication, and the capacity for social play; and multiple stereotypies of behaviour. The three most common forms of autism spectrum disorders (ASD) are classical autism; pervasive developmental disorder not otherwise specified (PDD-NOS); and Asperger's syndrome. Whereas children with, say, trisomy 21 (Down syndrome) or Williams syndrome can be abnormally sociable - and therefore rewarding to raise - by contrast autistic children with an absent or underdeveloped theory of mind commonly cause great distress to their caregivers. It is hard to bond with someone who always treats you as an object. Thus any genetic disposition to autism might seem a prime candidate for elimination from the gene-pool as the Reproductive Revolution gathers pace. However, some of the greatest scientists who ever lived, notably Newton, Einstein and Dirac, fulfill many or all of the diagnostic criteria for Asperger's syndrome. To what extent was their scientific acumen separable from their pathologies of mind?

      Calculating Risk-Reward Ratios

      If there are likely to be so many possible adverse and/or unintended consequences of the new reproductive medicine - and perhaps dystopian outcomes no one has even considered - then why forge ahead? Why not outlaw the new reproductive technologies altogether, or at least drastically restrict their use to simple Mendelian genetic diseases of the body rather than complex disorders of the mind/brain? After all, there is no way we can computationally model all the ramifications of even modest rewrites of the human genome.

      Here the question comes down to an analysis of risk-reward ratios - and our basic ethical values, themselves shaped by our evolutionary past. Lest extension of the new reproductive medicine seem too rashly experimental even to contemplate, it's worth recalling that each act of old-fashioned sexual reproduction is itself an untested genetic experiment, the outcome of random mutations and meiotic shuffling of the genetic deck, and with no happy ending to date. So just who are we to accuse of reckless gambling? As it stands, all of us are genetically predestined to grow old and die; and in the course of a lifetime, the great majority of humans will experience periods of intense psychological distress, for instance loneliness and heartache after an unhappy love affair. Our social primate biology ensures that most of us sometimes experience, to a greater or lesser degree, all manner of nasty states that were genetically adaptive in the ancestral environment e.g. jealousy, resentment, anger, and so forth. Hundreds of millions of people in the world today suffer bouts of depression; others live with chronic anxiety. One might say these phenotypes are part of what it means to be human. Worse, we pass a heritable predisposition to these horrible states on to our children.

      Bioconservatives, religious traditionalists, and social reformers alike would contest this bleak analysis. If you believe that human life today is fundamentally good, and viciously unpleasant states of mind are an aberration that can be mostly remedied by improving society, then you will need compelling reasons before wanting to change the regime of ordinary sexual reproduction as it exists now. Most likely, you will be loathe to support anything like the Reproductive Revolution predicted here; and focus entirely on its potential dangers. The spectre of "Brave New World" will probably loom large in any discussion. If, on the other hand, you think that Darwinian life is cruel and tragic by its very nature, then you are more likely to be willing to contemplate radical alternatives to the genetic status quo, despite the possible risks.

      My own view of the risks and uncertainties is that there is a critical distinction between trying to abolish suffering exclusively via social reform and abolishing suffering directly via biotechnology. As we know, utopian social experiments typically go wrong, sometimes hideously wrong, and end up causing a lot of suffering instead. The abolitionist project of eradicating the biological substrates of suffering sounds like just another utopian scheme, whether it's touted as a grandiose species-project or simply as a byproduct of the Reproductive Revolution explored here. Although the abolition of psychological pain is arguably no more utopian in principle than pain-free surgery, it could presumably go wrong in unanticipated ways too. Perhaps we'll unwittingly create a fool's paradise. But if and when we ever abolish the molecular underpinning of unpleasant experience, and it becomes physiologically impossible for any sentient being to suffer, we thereby change the very meaning of what it is for anything to "go wrong". Unwelcome surprises where no one gets hurt are very different from unwelcome surprises where they do. For what it's worth, I think the abolition of involuntary suffering is the precondition of any civilised posthuman society; and therefore a risk worth taking.

      The End of Sexual Reproduction?

      OK, I've outlined grounds for believing that our nastier Darwinian emotions will be selected against in future. Yet there is a fundamental objection to the argument from selection pressure that I've sketched so far. Surely most people, not least teenagers, will carry on producing babies by having sex together regardless of any so-called Reproductive Revolution of laboratory-mediated conception. Unplanned pregnancies are extremely common even in an age where contraceptives are widely available. Yes, maybe responsible, forward-looking parents will seek to ensure that they have children who are free of genetic handicaps, who are joyful, ultra-intelligent, super-empathetic and psychologically robust; and maybe in future such responsible parents-to-be will practise preimplantation genetic diagnosis, use germline gene therapy and pursue some of the futuristic interventions described here. But that won't stop feckless teenagers having unplanned babies. In addition, billions of people may be reluctant to embrace the new reproductive technologies for traditional moral or religious reasons, or simply out of custom and habit. It stretches the imagination to envisage genetically planned parenthood ever becoming as prevalent as, say, anaesthetics to guarantee pain-free surgery. If most fertile women continue to bear genetically unenriched babies by the conventional route, then surely our inbuilt genetic tendency to all forms of Darwinian suffering is going to express itself indefinitely?

      Maybe so. It's a powerful argument. Yet there are strong grounds for thinking that traditional-style sexual reproduction can't continue for more than a few generations. The reason is bound up with the coming revolution in antiaging medicine.

      Throughout most of human history, radical life-extension, let alone the prospect of eternal youth, has been the province of quacks and charlatans. To some extent it still is; swallowing a bunch of vitamin pills each day isn't going to let you live for ever. But over the next few centuries, and possibly before, aging and the genes that promote or allow senescence are going be phased out. This is of course a bold claim that I won't even attempt to defend in detail here. If you are sceptical and haven't read the book already, I'd recommend Aubrey de Grey's Ending Aging: The Rejuvenation Breakthroughs That Could Reverse Human Aging in Our Lifetime (2007). Now I am more pessimistic than Aubrey de Grey about timescales. Yet the genetic and pharmacological interventions that we are already trying in nonhuman animals will eventually be tried in the human animal too. One hesitates to embrace what sounds like a facile technological determinism; but I think we can say, quite dogmatically, that if and when radical antiaging technologies become available, then the overwhelming majority of people will use them - regardless of any rationalizations of death and aging we express now. Moreover most people will also want such treatments for their family pets; the Antiaging Revolution won't be confined to one species.

      Let's assume for the sake of argument that this is the case i.e. there will be both a Reproductive Revolution and an Antiaging Revolution. If post-genomic medicine dramatically extends lifespan, and fewer and fewer people die of the traditional diseases of old age, then our planet will soon reach its carrying capacity. Looking centuries ahead, a rapidly expanding population of eternally youthful quasi-immortals means that human reproduction of any kind will have to become rare, and eventually a momentous event, and tightly controlled in every respect. It's here that I foresee both the greatest ethical dilemmas arising from the Reproductive Revolution and also the intimate link between superhappiness, superintelligence and superlongevity.

      Selection Pressure in an Age of Quasi-Immortality

      When the Earth reaches its carrying capacity - the maximum packing density of sentient beings consistent with sustainable life - there will have to be immensely greater centralized control of the human reproductive system on pain of complete Malthusian catastrophe. This does indeed sound a truly sinister prediction. Perhaps one can imagine the existence of a mandatory regime of depot-contraception from an early age. Yet could depot-contraception really be made fail-safe? How would such fertility control be enforced? Moreover the problem isn't just preventing reproductive accidents. The urge to have one's "own" children can be extraordinarily strong, as attested by the anguish caused by involuntary childlessness today; and for many childless couples, this yearning could eclipse any general worries about the carrying capacity of the planet. A majority of people will want both to stay forever young and to have children. If radical antiaging technologies are indeed widely adopted, then a central and unavoidably intrusive control of human reproduction may be inevitable, though one may trust such powers will be accountable to democratic control. In an era of mass superlongevity, every intellectually competent citizen will presumably recognize, in the abstract, that unlimited free reproduction is physically impossible. On the other hand, some people will presumably try to have unregulated, unsanctioned children, just as they do in the People's Republic of China (PRC) today, albeit without the promise of eternal youth. This is not an attractive parallel. Of course there are other social perils associated with mass superlongevity: in an era of genetically pre-programmed eternal youth, the ruling power elites may prove almost immovable in the absence of adequate democratic safeguards. But the potential loss of bodily autonomy and procreative liberty is especially troubling to the liberal conscience - and to any libertarian life-extensionist.

      A counterargument here is that the urge to bear children is under genetic control; and that urge will itself be amenable to biological intervention. Manipulation of our first-order desires is likely to prove biologically easier than defeating aging. Yet if most of one's enhanced fellow citizens do act responsibly and forgo or postpone reproduction, then any predisposition to "cheat" and have children might be highly (genetically) adaptive, at least in the short-run. Such an outcome would be disastrous in an already overpopulated global megalopolis. Plausible group selectionist scenarios aren't easy to construct even for the far future. Hence the price of posthuman superlongevity is the likelihood of ever greater state intervention in the (hitherto) private realm - although such intrusiveness need not be subjectively distressing in any sense we would recognise today, since the functional analogue of distress might suffice. Long before any era of post-genomic medicine, Plato believed that human reproduction should be monitored and controlled by the state, a portent of totalitarian societies to come; but once we transcend the biology of human mortality, some sort of collective control of reproductive decision-making may prove inescapable even in a liberal democracy. The only alternative to such control would be draconian, state-enforced rationing of anti-aging therapies: a scarcely credible re-enactment of Logan's Run. It's important to note that this argument doesn't turn on whether it transpires that the ultimate carrying capacity of our planet is 15 billion, or 150 billion, or conceivably even higher packing densities. Yes, we can colonise the Solar System. In theory, too, in some era of the distant future, the authorities on Earth could tell anyone who wants to have a child that they must do so on one of the extrasolar planetary systems that we colonise. But for the next few centuries at least, and possibly millennia, the prospect of some kind of Galactic adaptive radiation is pure science-fiction. For it is hard to overstate the technical obstacles to mass interstellar travel. Quite possibly posthumans will go to the stars, and perhaps even colonise our local galactic supercluster in a few million years or so. Realistically, this doesn't solve the near-term demographic challenge of a massively overcrowded Earth.

      Admittedly I am making a number of contestable assumptions here. I will note just three. First, intelligent life won't wipe itself out altogether in the next few decades. [Doomsday scenarios are conceivable; but they are much harder to construct once self-sustaining colonies are established on other planets later this century.] Second, there is a unique past and a unique future. [This simplifying assumption is inconsistent with quantum cosmology and most likely false. However, consideration of the "branch density¡± measure of alternative, classically inequivalent histories in post-Everett quantum mechanics would take us too far afield in this talk.] Third, unlike futurists who believe in "uploading", I am assuming that our (post)human descendants will retain an organic substrate - maybe augmented by web-enabled neurochips, nanobots, bionic implants and the like - and hence that humans won't scan, digitize and "upload" themselves to dwell in another computational medium where the constraints of the Earth's ecosystem don't apply. [There is no evidence that your PC is any more conscious than an abacus, despite its greater processing power; and if a souped-up version of your PC contained a digitized representation of you, this would doubtless facilitate restoration from backups, but there are no grounds for thinking such lines of code would be conscious either - let alone "you". Yes, artificial intelligence will hasten the Reproductive Revolution; and perhaps one day we will all become web-enabled cyborgs. And who knows what kinds of exotic postbiological artificial life can be evolved if and when our descendants run mature quantum computers. Yet there is simply no evidence that inorganic systems with a classical von Neumann architecture support "raw feels" or intrinsically matter: the notion that our species might destructively upload ourselves from basement Reality into digital nirvana is unworkable.] So here at least I am being tamely bioconservative in assuming that the Earth 1000 years hence will support a densely populated primordial "meatworld" of our flesh-and-blood post-human descendants.

      Anyhow, to summarise, assume that the creation of new quasi-immortal beings will indeed become exceedingly rare later this millennium. The Earth will be (almost) literally full. I'd argue that on such historic occasions as the creation of a new posthuman-being, it is unlikely that superhappy, superintelligent agents will create the genetic malware for unpleasant, stupid, senile substrates of consciousness i.e. archaic Homo sapiens. Our posthuman descendants are more likely to create fellow "smart angels" instead. The triumph of the Reproductive Revolution will have reshaped the post-Darwinian fitness landscape beyond all recognition. Hence my (tentative) prediction that the biology of suffering and senescence is destined to pass into evolutionary history.

      David Pearce, 2009
      La revoluci¨®n reproductiva (Spanish tr.)
      Die reproduktive Revolution (German tr.)

      See also Liberal Eugenics?
      The Biointelligence Explosion (2012)


      The Abolitionist Project
      Refs
      and further reading

      Resources
      Talks 2015
      Eugenics.org
      BLTC Research
      Liberal Eugenics
      Superhappiness?
      Utopian Surgery?
      The End of Suffering
      Wirehead Hedonism
      Social Media (2023)
      The Good Drug Guide
      Paradise Engineering
      The Abolitionist Project
      Quora Answers (2015-23)
      The Hedonistic Imperative
      The Biointelligence Explosion
      MDMA: Utopian Pharmacology
      Full-Spectrum Superintelligence
      ChatGPT on the Reproductive Revolution
      The World Transhumanist Organization/H+
      Critique of Aldous Huxley's Brave New World
      Selection Pressure in a Post-Darwinian World (2): Gene Drives (2016)

      e-mail
      dave@hedweb.com

      ¡°You wait till Larry comes and I tell him my theory!¡± The bids, duly sealed, were given into the keeping of the commissary officer to be put in his safe, and kept until the day of judgment, when all being opened in public and in the presence of the aspirants, the lowest would[Pg 188] get the contract. It was a simple plan, and gave no more opportunity for underhand work than could be avoided. But there were opportunities for all that. It was barely possible¡ªthe thing had been done¡ªfor a commissary clerk or sergeant, desirous of adding to his pittance of pay, or of favoring a friend among the bidders, to tamper with the bids. By the same token there was no real reason why the commissary officer could not do it himself. Landor had never heard, or known, of such a case, but undoubtedly the way was there. It was a question of having the will and the possession of the safe keys. "Well, I believe our boys 's all right. They're green, and they're friskier than colts in a clover field, but they're all good stuff, and I believe we kin stand off any ordinary gang o' guerrillas. I'll chance it, anyhow. This's a mighty valuable train to risk, but it ought to go through, for we don't know how badly they may need it. You tell your engineer to go ahead carefully and give two long whistles if he sees anything dangerous." "Fine-looking lot of youngsters," he remarked. "They'll make good soldiers." "That's just what he was, the little runt, and we had the devil's own time finding him. What in Sam Hill did the Captain take him for, I'd like to know? Co. Q aint no nursery. Well, the bugler up at Brigade Headquarters blowed some sort of a call, and Skidmore wanted to know what it meant. They told him that it was an order for the youngest man in each company to come up there and get some milk for his coffee tomorrow morning, and butter for his bread. There was only enough issued for the youngest boys, and if he wanted his share he'd have to get a big hustle on him, for the feller whose nose he'd put out o' joint 'd try hard to get there ahead o' him, and get his share. So Skidmore went off at a dead run toward the sound of the bugle, with the boys looking after him and snickering. But he didn't come back at roll-call, nor at tattoo, and the smart Alecks begun to get scared, and abuse each other for setting up a job on a poor, innocent little boy. Osc Brewster and Ol Perry, who had been foremost in the trick had a fight as to which had been to blame. Taps come, and he didn't get back, and then we all became scared. I'd sent Jim Hunter over to Brigade Headquarters to look for him, but he came back, and said they hadn't seen anything of him there. Then I turned out the whole company to look for him. Of course, them too-awfully smart galoots of Co. A had to get very funny over our trouble. They asked why we didn't get the right kind of nurses for our company, that wouldn't let the members stray out of their sight? Why we didn't call the children in when the chickens went to roost, undress 'em, and tuck 'em in their little beds, and sing to 'em after they'd said 'Now I lay me down to sleep?' I stood it all until that big, hulking Pete Nasmith came down with a camp-kettle, which he was making ring like a bell, as he yelled out, 'Child lost! Child lost!' Behind him was Tub Rawlings singing, 'Empty's the cradle, baby's gone.' Then I pulled off my blouse and slung it into my tent, and told 'em there went my chevrons, and I was simply Scott Ralston, and able to lick any man in Co. A. One o' their Lieutenants came out and ordered them back to their quarters, and I deployed the company in a skirmish-line, and started 'em through the brush toward Brigade Headquarters. About three-quarters o' the way Osc Brewster and Ol Perry, when going through a thicket, heard a boy boo-hooing. They made their way to him, and there was little Skidmore sitting on a stump, completely confused and fagged out. He'd lost his way, and the more he tried to find it the worse he got turned around. They called out to him, and he blubbered out: 'Yes, it's me; little Pete Skidmore. Them doddurned fools in my company 've lost me, just as I've bin tellin' 'em right along they would, durn 'em.' Osc and Ol were so tickled at finding him that they gathered him up, and come whooping back to camp, carrying him every step of the way." And the rush stopped. Cadnan waited for a second, but there was no more. "Dara is not to die," he said. Then he saw Orion hanging over him, very low in the windy sky, shaking with frost. His eyes fixed themselves on the constellation, then gradually he became aware of the sides of a cart, of the smell of straw, of the movement of other bodies that sighed and stirred beside him. The physical experience was now complete, and soon the emotional had shaped itself. Memory came, rather sick. He remembered the fight, his terror, the flaming straw, the crowd that constricted and crushed him like a snake. His rage and hate rekindled, but this time without focus¡ªhe hated just everyone and everything. He hated the wheels which jolted him, his body because it was bruised, the other bodies round him, the stars that danced above him, those unknown footsteps that tramped beside him on the road. Farewell to Jane and Caroline!" HoME´óÏã½¶É«È˸ó ENTER NUMBET 0017
      www.shifa6.net.cn
      www.chaye5.net.cn
      siqi9.com.cn
      www.riye0.net.cn
      www.lgrm.net.cn
      art170.com.cn
      www.budou9.net.cn
      75ze.org.cn
      638576.org.cn
      www.mezui7.com.cn
      sex007dh 黄色以及金发大波 狠狠插衅小说 zui淫当的女人 在线电影西野翎 狠狠射套图 偷拍老外打野炮 能bt下载的黄色网址有什么 色无码电影 WWW.SHLSHW.COM WWW.AVTAOBAO.CA WWW.9ZY.COM WWW.BBB012.COM WWW.IKUYY.COM WWW.QIMI567.COM WWW.001561.COM WWW.CYMPZJ.COM WWW.XIAOMINGLU.COM WWW.QZXSHG.COM WWW.234ZA.COM WWW.DAKCN.COM WWW.LQCYSK.COM WWW.PNZWK.COM WWW.MMM70.COM WWW.223326.COM WWW.BBYLU.COM WWW.JSZXA.COM WWW.995NN.COM WWW.LWLM.COM WWW.9LALA.COM 偷拍打炮 亚洲电亚洲电影一级三级片 电车千人斩美女 9797sb 亚洲天堂姐姐图片 美女馒头缝 成人社www6666caocom 人体色色小色网 爱丽丝丝袜 大黑吊双非亚裔美女 91超碰自拍91agaobiz 在车上强奸黄色小说 555dvd版 4hu8ftp 乱伦孙婆在线97 天天日久久射精品 色网AV免费在线 三国影视韩国 xiao七七小说网 234XXXX mm付费影院 好硬啊受不了舒服快点嗯插揉捏舔换妻3p 非洲三级片大全 老师媳妇的性奴 三级片女秘书 丝袜黄色图片区 姬岛琉璃香在线观看 女儿当妻子乱伦 窝窝娱乐网 邪恶少女漫画全色彩群奸 尻bi 狠狠色无极 大姨子偷欢 231avav 草莓100视频在线播放caonila 风骚少妇掰开私处让你操 婷婷五月花亚洲色图 大爷av影院免费观看 色忧忧av国产 色姐姐色妹妹激情电影在线播放 12345cccom 播乐子超在线 免费伦理小说母子片 www7878kf 96色色 977AV在线视频 求免费成人电影app像猫咪av一样的 色月丁香网 5678台湾老伦理在线 wwwhw好日子啪啪 成人影院草榴 萝莉乱伦小说网站 3d欧美动漫 姑xx卡通 奇米影音第四色7e7ucom 都市激情乱伦小说在线看 亚洲武侠古典在线播放 julia超碰在线观看 wwwggg03 看到b的美女操b 亚洲儿童哭泣 国产第一页1024网址 婷婷夜夜撸 wwwbbb75com 干丰满少妇真爽 内射美女骚穴在线视频 最新免费成人性爱网址 猛男熟妇乱伦电影片 3p无码啪啪啪 日本少女激情电影兽欲 淫水流的老婆很骚下载 进进出出嫩穴p 三级无码高清 WWWRRR777COM 冲田杏梨的巨乳舔频屏吧 磁力链接成都兰桂坊 亚洲色图校长 外国妇女的阴部图展示 夜夜干夜夜go2048com 991色色直 亚洲成人综合综合套图校园春色 成人电影偷拍自拍亚洲图片欧美图 乱操逼 免费79dodo 熟女乱伦偷拍逼 taiwansexvideo 伎逼射精图怕 长谷川由奈写真 成人免费电影幼交同志 两性做爱图片哪里有 美国大胆电影 影音先锋人肏肏狗 宫如敏全套高清照片 庐江艳照门迅雷种子 与空共同生活24小时 狗鸡巴肏女人 激情诱惑美女影音先锋 人体艺木l 与淑女乱伦 日本大逼逼裸体艺术 32式夫妻性姿势动态图 婷婷五月成人社区 外国美女口交20p pisay pao演过什么 9da51f8e00001217 露出小屄了 强奸美女小屄 美女图片都不穿xiaoshuo 女教师厕所偷拍图片 乡村操穴小说 拍网友骚女人 父女叉屄 国外全裸演唱会视频 论理性与情感照片视频 人妻 亚洲 qvod 有没有阿娇的阴部图片 东北成人网论坛 五月天影院快播 磁力链接 在线播放 学生和老师天天做爱 斗战神猴子棍系加点 顾雅莉 阳光大姐月嫂培训 国家海洋局北海分局 插幼幼淫网 少妇美穴15p 操大黑逼逼 clsq123 欧美男图片吧 屄最黑女明星 幼种子zip 汤芳大胆艺术照 日本美女下体艺术摄影图 日本美女秀百屄图 美女丝袜密室狠狠撸色图 肉棒操骚逼 包射日本美女 小明看看最新手机页面 葵实野理无码流出 陪我撸影院播放 哥哥操图片 成人嘻嘻导航 WWWHHH097COM 乱了儿子 xingbiantaiwangzhan 谁空间内有爽图 操紧身妹 换妻母子 大胆女同性恋影级 伦理琪琪琪影 www38popoom 撸撸撸两炮 久爱微拍 新掌酷手机手机电影 超碰百年好合网址 老少男女乱伦 快活宫 淫荡美女情妇 偷偷鲁网友 三级片嫩模做爱视频成人片 偷偷撸狠狠撸在线色图 狠狠射性感美女屁股图片 撸操女人 奇米影视775me9999abc 日了妈妈和姐姐动漫 成人黄色电影国产片 征服刘亦菲母女 强奸乱伦AV网址 越南美女大胆裸体人体艺术 激情影院20秒试看 哥哥色cm 狼窝yingyuan 幼女与成人性生活小说 激情五月姐姐seffhhggcom 同学阿姨的美脚 偷怕自拍国产精品magnet 色g有声小说 三岔口有声小说 樱井莉亚学制精灵 h网 小说 开心五月天图 东京热0327 东京热怎么 5300看黄片 蝴蝶谷网 色色快播 色域H网 90聚导航 性生活知识 一个色电影 日本美腿丝袜 哇嘎成人社区 台湾佬中文娱乐网 欲望之城成人社区 777米奇 百撸 松本麻里奈中文字幕种子链接 超级轮乱家庭漫画 YOYO视频磁力链接 234top 色欲宗和合网 人人干人人操人人麽 女同天天啪 色爱52v 日本学生av 小乔影院福利地址 秋霞床上 性交视频极品 情欲媽 日本岳母大奶免费视频 日韩 偷拍 自拍 在线 在线 无码 国产自拍 丝袜 中文字幕 日本一本道在线免费看 日本曰B 日本女优和黑人操逼16p AV800000 2019AV云盘 0855kk 远坂凛 做爱 100名日本女优视频 人间中毒末册剪版在线 白户英里奈链接 男人你懂得在线看 午夜免费57 www179nncon 色鬼国内自拍在线观看 国产自拍在线成观看 免费黄色视频好屌色 222av tb 国产自拍磁力合计 电脑在线观看国产自拍 青青草鸡巴要要在线观看 china夫妻性 回校的地铁上撩起了女同座裙子漫画 久久爱水莱丽在线播放 熟女做爱图片小视屏 调教日记6 番号 坏木坏木木集百万潮流小说 639影院福利片 大尺度同志在线观看 youbbb/cm 影音先锋 91 娃玖电影手机在线 4438x免费成人网暴力 猪小明墙 大桥未久Av 在线 91老司机sm 柚木提娜剧情在线播放 决胜 magnet 处女失身记视频 福利影院闪现福利 大鸡巴小鲜肉约炮极品丝袜高跟美女玩角色扮 地下痴女3d链接 成人影院在观线看 大香蕉网站被老公的上司连续侵犯七天已经丧失理性 国产成人啪啪自拍 yuojii视频 4438Xx12C〇m 色女人偷拍 k8经典邱淑贞 mm小视频在线观看 色哥vvv68 4438x手机在线观看 www奔驰宝马成人网站 日本搭讪在线视频 泽艺影院在线观看 主播网红在线影院 3D动漫成人视频 91大神C仔之极品黑丝高跟年轻豪门女家教 教育网人体艺术 香港奥门a片 国产自拍在线播放无需播放器 乱伦人妻在线视频 52秒拍福利视频优衣库 日韩无码欧美在线丝袜百度云 岛国爱情动作片卵蛋 7777,gao,com 拍拍影院三级片 韩国青草 4480国产自拍三级 现在能看黄色视频的播放器 小V欲女规视频 想要零用钱妹妹帮素股。结果爽到自行插入肉到爽番号 性交视频网战 校院武侠作爱视频 久草特黄免费视频 温碧霞b cup 国产偷拍亚洲华人自拍 美丽人妻少妇被插视频 成人黄色一级电视剧 A片红 楼 肏b视频 操好丝袜 国内自拍性交视频 仓持结爱高潮跌幅湿漉漉的性爱 视频密码 哥爱搞搞网在线看 美国伦理精彩剪辑在线 有没有a片网站 羔羊医生 magnet 我的性感女秘书窝窝伦理电影 厕所直插下面视频 被窝理论电影300集 sm 亚洲 欧美 少妇 女神平面模特李x熙视频 插美少妇小穴 杨幂在线永久视频在线 网红花臂纹身美女大花猫SM微拍视频 ddd528kkk 日本版红楼梦成人在线 情趣磁力 magnet 日本老女人丝祙 俺去啦在线不要播放器 做爱视频鸡吧插的好舒服啊 同性在线播放 宅男成人福利网址导航 袭击女教师水菜丽在线看 全世界最火的小黄片视频网站 feexx 有欧美爆乳的电影 主播 磁力链接 mp4 亚洲最大福利视频道网 苍进空磁力链接下载 国产系医生护士搞在线 女生资源 91日逼视 免费天海翼视频在线观看 暗拍美女潜规则视频 国产网红主播激情自拍 悠悠色播 免费成人斤 成人手机视频5× 日本强奸妇女有哪些在线视频 国产中老年男同视频在线观看 Xxx经典国语网 美女被黑人操音乐 色欧美免费小视频 六月丁香深深爱在线 青青草大香蕉公开视频 家庭乱情王玉霞 aaa47大片 黄瓜视频官网 好看成人短视频 片a本日女小妹 9200dy 韩国男女搞基直播 日本老熟妇性欲 setongxue 帅哥抽插 悠悠av资源 骑手黄色网站 乐播av 成人网战链接 水仙网罗马影音先锋 人与兽bt种子 下载 秘杜mmsscom 国产自拍免费播放网站 好屌操在线影院 国产在线俱乐部 a片降头电影 x25rrrr 女人摸自己的阴天天影音 惹惹成人视屏 北条麻妃无码神马在线观看 无码性爱视频播放器 在线屋里番在线观看 wohejiaoshimamadeseqinggushi 77mp4 sixt 小身材影音先锋 秋霞无码理论欧美电影 4480福利动作影院 日本成人性爱视频在线 caoporn视频在线 国产自拍 三级黄久久免费视频 大黑逼色导航 和幼女做爱英语怎么说 美少女操屄图片 huangseyijipianwuzetian 哪里能看到乱伦小说 kaixinjiqingwangzhan 淫色基地成人电影 李宗瑞刘亦菲 学姐教会我内射 干熟女大屁股 天天射综合网 天天射 护士做爱艳照 qq阴茎表情 9797滛滛网 张雨筱露逼图片 极品少妇乱淫 色丑月 激情妹妹狠操社区 雯雅婷 p 胆大人体阴道 美女医生的性生活故事 熟女俱乐部母子家庭乱伦 欧美老女人爱大炮 小泽玛利亚经典是哪一部 外国女人的阴道比中国女人的大 波多野结衣酒店性爱图片 花花操逼 性爱网亚洲 波多野结衣蝴蝶逼 哪个主播露点 看日bb电影 路边偷拍美女脱丝袜 亚洲美女bb人体艺术大bb图片精选 少妇肉体视频图片小说 全球最美阴毛彩绘百度 脱摸吻揉舔插射爽 最新先锋强奸乱伦 sao1314next 美女的逼骚吗 a片 迅雷下载 ok3699jiunengshuangle 重庆赵红霞真实照片 钮扣包装机 cs15中文版官方下载 为自己疗伤 裸体照下面带毛 夫妻口交视频 换妻群交老婆被干了 西西美女写真人体艺术 内射粉木耳图 性感h漫女 做爱图片大全 黑人抽插女大学生 台湾天目为何油亮是否对人体有害 长谷川惠美全裸图片 偷拍走光露逼 性感的公鸡在日本爱 日本女优吉吉 欧美huangsetupian 肥胖大妈试玩一下16p 张筱宇裸体图 14岁少女午夜操逼逼图 1919go全集wctoupai 美女明星内地艳门照被奸 莲苍h 日本香奈图片 恒荣半岛影院 吃六神丸壮阳吗 有一部日本a片变态 大自由门 玩女人逼爽吗 陆婷婷的新故事 类似91pore 橘梨纱pron 少妇成熟高跟 美女露b人体艺术图片 和骚人妻偷情 另类偷拍自拍女厕所 亚洲情图片插插 妹妹水好多三级片 tube8jianpanhome 欧美孕妇裸体写真 女人美穴图片 苍井空av电影里快播 亚洲操逼辣图 欧美人体露美穴图片 WWWZ9191COM 十五岁女孩嫩穴 影音先锋草p片 色成人激情小说 中华明星合成联盟 强奸幼女小说淫魔 欧激情美 插入成人图 色qing3jipian 苍井そら 全97本番 エスワン12时间コンプリ━萣est av撸色2013 谁有一本道的网站 rtys人体艺术 kaori无码 发红屄 快乐网 亿性家社区视频 放心医院两性真人视频 女神约泡系列 成人影ya 叶子楣人体写真下载 母子猛干 女主播水仙先锋影音 wwese华人视频com 看电影lai5566 伦理微电影magnet 快播变态女子监狱 绿色无毒的av电影网址 亚洲偷少妇偷拍网 淫荡艳妻 xzzlynmp4 pv990下载地址 婷色艺术 日本涩情pia 欧美激情丝袜电影 操台湾妹子综合网站 欧美超爽图 欧美熟女高跟骚屄 大波少妇背着老公与我偷情自拍 kukucao网址 ab偷拍自拍 色五月激情五月开心五月开心色播深爱五月色播五月 插逼进行操 SM之拳交妹妹后庭花 黑人大吊手机影视 干里赖你个集掰你个蓝交 av插肛视频播放 酷娱乐影视 日本大胆av人体写真 当着外人的面插入下载 淫荡的性奴熟妇 人妻野外调教小说 美味的邂逅秒播影视 淫色娟娟 36d大乃网欧美AV视频 美女奶子videombaiducom 我妹让我插进去了图 www2C33eeecom cqopor 人狗大战伦理片下载 偸拍女性上厕所大便 姐姐性教育之熟女 宝来美雪ed2k 亚洲电亚洲电影一级三级片 华为网盘饭岛爱 色一涩888手机版 AV教师有中文字幕 人肉医奴隶 夜猫免费视频在线观看 哥想撸久草 极品少妇赤裸自慰 videos日本小女孩 能免费看av的软件 俩性生活迅雷下载图片 白色帝国论坛 久草手机在线观视频dz003com 英语老师小骚货 岳母比老婆好中文字幕 激情五月色视频www031ncom 家庭乱伦丝袜文章 金瓶梅成人性爱电影 s3zzbbcom xedd5com 性奴玛丽奥特曼 深圳合租房换女妻 久久爱情电影 超碰邻居熟女自拍偷拍在线 母子乱伦自拍网站 h七七p七cn 中出人妻20P 偷干人妻网 www69avcom 成人三级图 光棍电影手机观看小姨子 插入技巧小说 360色图 日本网站网站大全A片wwwc5508com 日本打炮射精热视频 黑人影院无需播放器 2233p x77135com 少女日本电影影音先锋 日韩av手机在线 头交是真的还是假的 麻生希婚纱影音先锋 欧美成人图像 888840c○m 在线卡通第一页 天天啪啪 日本AV色星熟女英文名排行榜 最大淫网 [18P]下一篇 线上干短片 搜索wwwjjxxoocom DBEB045 色色妹7 人人dvd 美国色图操操操 av天堂1024 苍月战士一路向西 人体mrtzcc 换妻日逼片 国产偷拍亚洲Av 苹果范冰冰电影完整 妹妹五月四房色伯图片 淫荡激情夫妻书库 3p性交 W66cccom 绑作者不详 啪啪啪在线兔费 草莓影音免费视频在线观看 关于处女破处的三级片 vvvv900 h动漫电梯小姐在线观看 www·bbb866·com下载 干女人逼视频在线 色少妇巨乳www23xxoocom 大鸡吧老公操动态图片 Www撸妹妹撸 男人体艺术偷拍 幼童H网 想屄图 美咲结衣重口味 大片上床 地下歌舞团黑酒吧演出 被迫坐肉棒 下鸡巴操屄p 裸体少女的屄 日本电影父女乱 白石瞳百度音影 熟女 性爱影院 888kkkk mimisechengrendaohang 呦呦同志种子 caoxisaobi 美女爱上大屌球 舒淇人体阴部 � 老婆和女儿的小穴 操小姐小嫩逼 老农和几个大学色女生的淫荡生活 波多野结衣洗澡做爱 狠狠色欧美色图 丝袜淫乱都市 东京热吉吉影音2233b 123美女se图 美少女色片 第四色 高清裸体炮图 ww777cccc777 鱼鱼发乱伦有声小说 华人家庭乱伦小说 � 跪求张柏芝艳照门视频 色 五月天 婷婷人与动物 美妇图册熟女相册 2015最新黄色笑话 成人在线国外 黑b 舔岳母亲 肥穴h图 xxoous你懂的小说 WWW_MAYAW_COM a片合集迅雷合集 操五十八岁大妈快播 多原爱 富士康厂妹qq群 cs16地图编辑器 poynjizzjizzpoyn 插女子网 吉吉av色片 新闻两片嫩肉 红音萤影音先锋 同性恋操屁股的图片 黄色网址无簿日韩 性爱狠撸撸小说 鸡巴肏屄的图片 seqingshi频 我和小姐乱伦 狠狠干自拍 明星合成王艳 芭芭拉人体艺术第一季 撸撸撸射 学校骚妇被插爽了 撸哥妹短片在线 强奸同学母小说 教师操屄 av小池郎 藤田凉子黑人 法哥操美女 张柏芝qovd完整版 上海自然博物馆4d影院 把屄拍照给别人看的感觉 泽国中学叶坚强老师的照片谁有 玩弄姚笛的屁眼 性交真人视频过程 插黑木耳高清图片18p 什么浏览器能下载嘼交片啊 svssex 淫姐姐色色电影网站 弟弟用力插妹妹 冰冷热带鱼146分钟种子 18xx24cccc 操苍井空嫩屄 七七色原图 小姨子的神秘三角地带 吉吉成人影沓 黑丝足txt 风流老徐娘15P 操十岁幼nv小说 四房播播伦理片 偷拍网国产视频m520xxbinfo 韩国女主播干妹妹 空姐干爹 长篇连载淫荡人妻驱灵师 有强奸内容的小黄文 大肛门欧美 尤丁香在线 青楼社区强奸 btyy sx黄色 反恐精英伊莎邪恶图片 白洁骆冰 青春少女下阴全裸图片 小明看看奥门 干漂亮老婆作者不详 都市激情亚洲色图花和尚 gggg555成人网 插妈妈在线视 欧美暴力性爱AV 日韩成人另类在线视频 日撸百度 恋母爱诗 真抢实弹福生日 韩国露点女主播有哪些 我的女朋友叫我搞她妈妈 熟年夫妇性爱日记 性春馆剑道 中文字幕影ckplayer在线观看 韩日女优大奶视频 手机快播能看的h网 快播h网大全 开心五月天激网 l酒色网 最近老看黄片 撸撸黄色小说 色五月激情五月天 浪妹社区 90后电影 我淫我乐综合 绝色影吧(荐) 爱搞机 凹凸AV电影手机在线下载 爱的色放西瓜 凉宫琴音在线看 动态图玉免社会app下载 人人草人人做 女大学生破处黄色视频 全裸美女照正面视频发 秋霞电影网伦理片手机版 青青情侣自拍视频在线 曰本黄大片p在线 淫撸女 影音先锋 熟女系列 日本乳汁作爱视频 日本亚洲欧洲另类 hd porn 91亚洲 轮奸骚逼太爽了大骚逼 韩国女主播 平台大全 姐汁 情艺中心在线紧急 这个杀手不太冷动态壁纸 4438×全国最大电 大尺度捏胸揉胸漫画 灰色毛衣在线完整版 国产欧美自拍 国模私拍露点视频 666668888888福利视频 近亲相奸大作战番号 日本AV黄图 mp4 让我添大胸添屁股的视频 亚洲不卡视频大全 女人乳头穿环视频播放 免费xing直播 黄色视频激情小说 热产热国产自拍 极品辣妈淫语约炮 旧谷露影院av欧美 亚洲视频人妻 丁香夜色 自拍骚逼 mp4 黑人影片三级黄色 717伦理片午夜福利剧场 猫味网站 无码背得心色香 毛片高清免费完整版1080p 87国产一区 91 E杯气美女 一色屋色色资源站 好色电影院菲菲 精子窝 网红主播自慰视频 武侠古典 万色屋 大香蕉福利电影 福利莫青视频在线 大香蕉丝袜亚洲国产 大香蕉95视频在线 yazhousutu 饭冈加奈子强制生中出 日本一级色片 李丽珍在线电影 magnet 久久爱视频10 粗大的做爱体验 我和阿姨乱伦视频 丁香五月在线观看线 成人丁香五月 百度 抽插在线视频 婷婷视频在线观看 福利资源大厅 艺校小女生在线视频 黑色男女福利 啪啪久啪啪精品99 淫湿影院 啪啪啪视频免费在线观看无码 日本少妇在家被强奷 偷拍自插 理论韩影库 wwwabc300cd 欧美AV日韩AV国产AV在,线 午夜情深深医院 1138x成年网 操丰满浪叫在线 京香中文字幕无删减 中国javhd 蝌蚪网无限看视频 AISS模特索菲 在线福利视频 女a片 拍拍拍噜噜噜 轻经操穴视频视 高清无码在线免安装 一路夜蒲 bt 相对宇宙 露点 求番号大胸妹子被裸体关在门外然后被强奸 秋霞电影网达达网 2综合色 色无极偷窥 av圣爱天堂2014 怡红院成人av电影 团鬼六拷问贵夫人 我肏小姨子的嫩屄 百变女神魅心户外大马路 萝莉自慰视频大全 小明发看看加密网址一 天狼影院三级片 1313电影网韩国演义圈 小孕妇seamp孕交 先锋影音冲田杏梨骑乘 淫秽视屏 五福影院其它地址 高清自拍尿尿 magnet 找av123导航 午夜按摩中字 大白逼做爱视频 和ye123一样的网站 uu福利 !密码 www,477,mm,con rosi视频002 快乐色 偷窥自拍777 色香蕉无码色 国产自拍在线诱惑 国语高清居家享受嗲嗲的女友口爆服务 国产偷拍白拍 自拍自摸国产 h0930 番号 丁香茶五月天 caoporn未满 色色色干人人 被窝屋 苹果手机成人免费视频 美女路b沟视频 找性交小姐性交巴西 俄罗斯最骚最黄的黄色录像视频 天天吊妞o 3344rq最新地址 啪啪啪视频网站上去衣图片给我看看你的照片看看你现在在哪里番acg 乳头文胸性诱惑 女神操逼视频在线 韩国女主播和闺蜜爱抚 网红啪啪啪视频大全 巴西做爱视频 家教老师秘书空姐护士美女满足表情性高潮视频 ROSI在线播放VIP 操逼福利区 国内第一人重口变态女王周晓琳 本庄优花黑人在线 老外啪啪内射视频 恋夜秀场美女同性恋做爱视频 四虎影院手机小视频福利 静宸制服私拍 赵铬扯肚兒视频 美国炮长 本站立足于 ooxxwangzhan mb27ba0 情人天堂 立足于美利坚合众国鲁 青青社区国产自拍 淫操初音女神 纯h视频免费 色佬久爱视频av天天看 色博士 色妞妞线官网 伦理片2344 色麒麟无码帝国av影院 毛片a片鸡巴插洞 美国偷拍三级网站酒店叫服务打飞机 精品操B 伦理福利在线365 李美淑左爱 都市激情校园人妻亚洲 黑丝袜伦理 韩国人做爱免费视频 欧美黑人性生活一级黄片 最近上传最新视频在线观看 蛇精潮巢漫画 freepronvv 激情小说激情图片激情电影 老色鬼导航最全面 冲田杏梨巨乳女教师91 偶偶福利电影 黄色小视频美利坚合众国 飘花影院ipad 黑哥tv登录740 好深好烫好棒顶到不行 好看做爱视频 今永纱奈AV电影迅雷 下载 夫妻露脸偷窥自拍 xingjiaomuzi 毛片123 dd55aa FC2云播手机在线 sex video ht 18禁无码里番在线观看 国内自拍 淫荡骚逼 有关性爱视频 郑州酒店有小姐决赛开始视频让妻子看什么连续剧播放视频 美女教师种子下载 mp4 日本三人交视频yes 秘杜mmsscom 秒播福利手机在线播放 好屌丝好屌操 韩国女主播CK买肉舞 国产偷拍少妇磁力迅雷下载 古装三级伦理在线电影 欧美影院高清 在线免费小视屏 色色风在线播放 日本a级无码 zaixianshipin wuma 大吊色 黄图香蕉影院 成人福利分享 髛屄视频 早乙女由依(萝莉) 777奇米影天堂 超成人触碰 穿连体袜的素人完整版 欧美一本道无码高清视频 日本sm在线调教视频 omeidonwu qj无码 世界最大胆美女人体艺术 人体艺术激情欧美 时间停止器系列先锋 黑木麻衣社长 日撸神 亚洲色图台湾佬 大胆人体艺术韩国美女明星图片 义弟内射嫂子 www骚嫂子com 国亩欢大胆露阴毛 成人大尺度gif 妇乱艺术穴图 公然妄想曝苍井空先锋影音 卖屄俱乐部 关之琳演过哪些三影级 韩青青医生 黑人夫妇宾馆作爱视频 哪里有韩国女主播种子 偷拍男按摩师视频